Facebook
users who believe that social networks are not legitimate venues
for lengthy exchanges (dismissively, I have found, termed “walls of
text”), or who are unable or unwilling to meticulously and
charitably review opinions that run contrary to their own, are
strongly advised against reading further. My complicated response is,
in truth, a compliment to the original poster. For I have taken his
remarks seriously enough to think about them at great length. And I
have had respect enough for his efforts to take the time to formulate
(the beginnings of) a reply. This reply, one may infer from the date
and time stamp, was not fired off-the-cuff. I ask only that persons
who, despite my advisory, decide to invest some of their very limited
time on this earth reading my reply, will show me the same courtesy
that I have shown for Mike. To be precise, I ask only that readers
not go off half-cocked merely because they're put out that someone
has dared to insinuate that Christianity is rationally defensible after
all. I take my intellectual obligations seriously, and I expect the
same from my interlocutors.
“Where the reader is as certain as I
am, he may accompany me; where, like me, he hesitates, he may
question me; when he sees himself in error, he may follow me; where I
go wrong, he may lead me back.” ~ St. Augustine, De Trinitate.
***
Three
preliminary remarks are in order.
Firstly,
I am sympathetic to several of your complaints. For example, I think
that your suspicion is well-grounded that “...Jesus would abhor the
lifestyles and behavior of most Americans, especially those who claim
to be Christians.” Additionally, there is no love lost between me
and moral subjectivism. Hence, I concur with your thought that the
untutored and often capricious “opinions” of people regarding the
Good are a woefully inadequate foundation on which to build a
culture's moral superstructure. Furthermore, despite what may appear
to be my rather severe verdict (following) on many of your
assertions, nonetheless, I share your enthusiasm for the free
exchange of ideas, I applaud your efforts to express your points by
way of analogy and thought experiment, and I trust, both from past
experience with you and from observation, that you realize that any
attack on your statements is not tantamount to an attack on you,
personally.
That
said I note, secondly, that it is at times difficult (for me at
least) to know precisely how to construe your text. To begin, greater
care must be taken to avoid confusing readers (at best) or spewing
nonsense (at worst). For example, as the text stands there is at
least one logical contradiction [See: END NOTE #1 for a definition of
“logical contradiction”], the presence of which throws a question
mark behind the intelligibility of a crucial couple of paragraphs –
to say nothing of the very coherence of the piece.
To
be precise, in one place you appear to stipulate the following
definition: “The definition of the word 'Christian' is one who
believes that Jesus of Nazareth is the divine son of the God of
Abraham.” Let this be “S”: “A Christian is a person who
believes that Jesus of Nazareth is the divine son of the God of
Abraham.” Further along, you write: “..Believing that Jesus was
the son of God doesn't make you a Christian.” In variable
assignment, this looks like it should be “not-S.” Now I am
confused. First you stipulated that a Christian is a person who
believes that Jesus of Nazareth is the divine son of the God of
Abraham, but now you take it all back. Hence, you say that it both is
and is not the case that a Christian is a person who believes in
Jesus of Nazareth in a particular way. To put it another way, you
have asserted Both S and not-S. This is a contradiction.
Perhaps
you meant to attribute “S” to your opponents without endorsing it
yourself. Perhaps one sentence contains a typographical error
(possibly). Probably, a bit more care during the editing
process would have prevented this sort of rather egregious error. At
the very least, however, you will have to address problems of this
sort prior to expecting that you have laid down anything like even a
minimal challenge to Christians (or to anyone else, for that matter),
let alone said something “definitive.”
However,
rectifying, excising, or otherwise setting aside this logical
blunder, the text has a hasty feel to it, overall, and many of the
assertions seem to have been shot from the hip.
To
give just a few quick examples, I observe that you began one
paragraph with an overheated claim about what “Most people
who call themselves 'Christian' believe...”. I say “overheated”
because, of course, even by the (arguably lax) standards of Wikipedia
such a statement would be flagged due to inadequate evidence. From
what sociological study do you draw these conclusions about what
“most Christians” believe? Are you reckoning “Christians”
according to your own (very idiosyncratic) definition, or according
to some other, more neutral definition? And there are other questions
besides.
Additionally,
you give varying – and non-equivalent – accounts of a matter that
is literally critical to your overall complaint (as nearly as I can
follow it). To be specific, in one place you claim that to be a
“Christian” (in your sense) one “must live by the tenets
of Christianity”. Elsewhere, however, you put what looks like it
was supposed to be the same point in different language, ostensibly
claiming that being a “Christian” (again, presumably in your
sense) requires that one “want to live by every tenet of
[Christianity]”. We need to be quite clear that statements like
“living according to x”, “necessarily living
according to x”, and “wanting to live according to x”
are making distinct claims. For example, the statement “living
according to x” is, straightforwardly, a matter-of-fact claim about
a particular way of living and does not involve matters of necessity
(“must”) or desire (“wanting”). Hence, when you
unceremoniously shift between statements your point becomes unclear.
Moreover, the distinct claims are not obviously related to each other
in any principled or predictable way. To give just a single
illustration, a person could very well live according to some
standard (x), in fact, without wanting to do so. Perhaps the
person is forced to live that way, for instance, but despises it.
Furthermore,
a number of your phrases are idiosyncratic, and could benefit greatly
from a concerted clarification effort. For example, it isn't
altogether obvious what you mean by constructions such as
“comprehensively familiar with every word” or “Jesus did not
subscribe to the concept of private property, but quite the
opposite.” “Comprehensive familiarity” seems either oxymoronic
or redundant. Given this possible duality of meaning, strictly
speaking, your phrase is ambiguous and stands in need of
disambiguation. In any case, in PART THREE I will take up the
question of whether the Christian need take seriously the redundant
sense (ignoring the possibility that the term is an oxymoron). [END
NOTE # 2]
Moreover,
it is not clear to me exactly how to take your mention of “the
concept of private property” and its alleged “opposite”. For one thing, it seems very doubtful that there is
much substance to the idea that there is one notion of “private
property” such that that notion and only that notion answers to the
definite description “THE concept of private property”. More
seriously, the various modern notions of private property arose quite
late in the history of philosophy. It is enormously anachronistic to
attribute to first century Palestinian Jews opinions on a
constellation of concepts that weren't even formulated until hundreds
of years later.
Thirdly,
it is worth underscoring that, insofar as some of your central points
are assertions, they stand in need of adequate defense (to say
nothing of clearer formulation) before readers (of any
persuasion) are put under any rational obligation to respond.
Although
I will try to frame my reply post in precise language, because of the
unstructured nature of the text that I am addressing, my own response
might sometimes read more like the various other “reactions” that
have collected underneath of it than the tight arguments that I
usually aim to produce. Moreover, given the wide ranging nature of
your assertions, I will necessarily be selective about the points
that I address, and I will be limited in terms of the depth with
which I am able to excavate any given point. Surely, if you sharpen
up your own text, I could do likewise with my response. And if you
focus your points, we could achieve greater depth in the dialectic.
From
here on I will ignore the more sensational difficulties (like the
aforementioned contradiction), and I will try to highlight a few of
(what I detect to be) the main conceptual difficulties in your
presentation. Time limitations (of mine) and miscellaneous limitations (e.g., of readers' patience) will
necessitate that I be brief (in my sense!). In what follows I will
not attempt an exhaustive reply. For one thing, as I have said, in
its present state your text is nowhere near complete (or coherent)
enough to warrant such an effort. Instead, I will merely try to make
a few issues salient and to give some indication of the complexity
that you have neglected – intentionally or unintentionally. In the
end, I am confident that you could retool your presentation and
provide respectable defenses for many (but not quite all, I am
afraid) of your points (if, again, I have rightly understood any of
them in this embryonic form).
Understand:
My reply represents quite an investment of time on my part. I would
not have bothered with this endeavor at all if I did not respect your
efforts.
The
remainder of my text will be divided into three main parts. In part
one, I will bring to your attention two confusions or conflations.
In places, you arguably conflate accidental properties and essential
properties; and, at times, you seem to confuse epistemological issues
with metaphysical issues. In part two, I will address several areas
where you oversimplify the issues in various respects. Specifically,
I will focus on three particularly weighty oversimplifications:
regarding issues of classification, regarding the provision of
an adequate account of liberty, and regarding the function of,
and need for, interpretation. In part three, I will issue a
warning against the perennial debating error of attacking straw men.
Straw man attacks may arise due to descriptions of the opposition
that are stipulated, as many of yours seem to be, and ascribed to
the opposition, without due consideration for the way the opposition
describes itself. Finally, I will provide a few brief closing
remarks.
PART
ONE – CONFUSIONS/CONFLATIONS
Subsection
A: The conflation of accidental properties and essential properties.
Let's
establish the requisite terminology. “The essential properties of a
thing...are those properties that it must have so long as it exists
at all... The accidental properties of a thing, by contrast, are
those properties that it could exist without.” [END NOTE # 3]
We
can illustrate this distinction by modifying your remarks about
birds.
You
wrote: >>...Believing that Jesus was the son of God doesn't
make you a Christian any more than believing you can fly makes you a
bird. You must fly to be a bird.<<
The
chief problem with your presentation of this example is that,
arguably, in it you conflate the essential property/accidental
property distinction. To be more exact, if being able to fly were an
essential property of a bird – that is, a property without which an
entity could not be a bird – then we should not have any sensible
specimens of birds that do not fly. Yet, this is not the case.
In
the first place, by the received view of taxonomy, there are several
respectable varieties of flightless birds. Two examples would
be penguins and ostriches. [END NOTE # 4]
Setting
aside so-called flightless birds for a moment, there is yet another
reason why the statement “You must fly to be a bird” is false.
Consider a newly hatched baby bluebird. According to your principle
(taken at face-value), it turns out that a newly hatched baby
bluebird isn't a bird. For a newly hatched baby bluebird can't -
actually - fly. But this is clearly (and I hope obviously) wrong.
However,
one might immediately object that I am straining out gnats. Clearly
your serious contrast is supposed to be between belief and
reality. And with this distinction I have great sympathy.
Probably,
you meant to write something more like that believing that one is
a bird does not make one a bird. To be a bird an entity must be
a bird, in fact; and not merely believe that one is a
bird.
Notice,
though, what happens to the illustration when this change is
implemented. As long as we keep an eye on the distinction between
essential properties and accidental properties, we see that an entity
counts as a bird just in case a bird is what the entity *is*, not
because of what the entity does or does not do, and
certainly not because of what the entity believes or does not
believe. (Possibly, a contrast could be developed along the lines of
potentiality, however.)
Two
further comments are in order.
Number
one, observation of the essence/accident distinction provides the
Christian with a reply to the thrust of your complaint, here. A
Christian could maintain that, just as a flightless bird is still a
bird (even if the bird is, in an important sense physically crippled,
or if the thing only “feels like” a bird in some demoted
sense of “bird”), in an analogous way, a “disobedient
Christian” is still a Christian (even if the Christian is, in an
important sense spiritually crippled, or if the Christian only
“feels like” one in some demoted sense of “Christian”).
I fail to see how you have even remotely foreclosed on this possible
avenue of response.
Number
two again, for all that you have said so far, a Christian could argue
that birds and Christians are relevantly different such
that, even if you could somehow remedy your analogy and press
home your desired point, still, the Christian would incur no
liability. Indeed, there is a straightforward way for the Christian
to accomplish this. I will take up this second possible Christian
line in the PART TWO, Subsection A.
Subsection
B: The confusion of epistemological issues and metaphysical issues.
“Epistemological
questions” are questions having to do with how a person can know
something. “Metaphsyical questions” are questions having
to do with what something *is*. The asterisks around the “is”
indicate that the word is to be read with suitable gravity in order
to grasp the meaning.
On
reflection, I think that it might be open to argue that your text is
shot-through with this species of confusion. However, perhaps one of
the more striking and obvious examples of the epistemic-metaphysic
confusion is the following.
You
wrote: >>The fact of the matter is, Christianity, and the
teachings of Jesus, originate in the Bible.<<
Let
me set up the criticism. A number of people – theists and
non-theists alike – believe that Jesus was an actual, “historical”
person who lived oh, say, from somewhere about 6 BC/AD 1 to
about AD 26/AD 33 (or thereabouts). On the general surmise that there
was a “historical Jesus” (which, as far as I can tell, you have
not argued against), about 2,000 years ago Jesus would have walked
about, eaten, said various things, and so on.
Straightforwardly,
then, “the fact of the matter is” that Jesus' teachings, and the
Church (Christianity) that he founded, “originate” with the
person himself, i.e., Jesus. This is a metaphysical point.
If Jesus did live and establish a church
(and so on), then that church originated with him. It would
still have originated with him even if that church had never been
written about (e.g., in the Bible). Without the Bible, today we might
not know that it existed (or that it had existed), but
this is another matter – an epistemic matter.
It
may be your intention to say that most modern people come to know
about Jesus through the Bible. This is an epistemic point. It
may be true or not. (In fact, I think that quite a few people learn
about Jesus through the Church or family, wholly apart from the
Bible, but I will ignore this.) The key point, however, is that one must
not confuse the Bible's being the origin for our (contemporary)
knowledge about (early) Christianity with the Bible itself
being the “origin” of Christianity itself or Jesus himself. Or, to use a
bit of jargon, this would be to confuse epistemology with
metaphysics.
One
might be able to see this distinction more clearly with an example.
What reply would predictably follow if, for example, I were to say,
parroting your statement: “The fact of the matter is biological
evolution through random mutation and natural selection, and the
teachings of Darwin, originate in The Origin of Species.”
Clearly, the predictable response is that, if biological evolution
through random mutation and natural selection is a true account of
the development of life on earth, such did not “originate” in The
Origin of Species – or in any other book – even if it is true
to say that we learned about it by reading that book. If true, it
“originated” in the actual development of organisms over hundreds
of millions of years of earth's history. If it is true, it's because, well, that's just what happened.
The
moral of the story is that the origin of our knowledge of x is
not necessarily the same thing as the origin of x itself.
Part
two – Oversimplifications
Subsection
A: Simplifications regarding issues of classification.
In
your text you mention a number of examples having to do with
classification. In general, by “classification” I mean some
principled way of determining what counts as what. For example,
following you, we might be concerned with whether some entity is a
bird or not, some female is pregnant or isn't, some person is a
Christian or not, or whether some law is Constitutional or
unconstitutional.
On
the subject of birds, let me pick up a strand from earlier.
Previously, I indicated that one possible line of response to your
bird analogy would be to simply label your original analogy faulty,
redraw it, and show that on the redrawn analogy it actually makes
good sense to suppose that some Christians fail to act as Christians
ought.
However,
I also hinted at a second line, which I will unpack presently. The
second line begins, as I already noted, by maintaining that birds
and Christians are relevantly different such that, even if you
could somehow remedy your analogy and press home your desired
point, still, the Christian would incur no liability. I further
stated that the there was a well known way to establish this
difference. That way involves the notion of “natural kinds.”
To
be precise, the Christian could argue that “bird” is a natural
kind term whereas “Christian” is not. Roughly, “natural
kinds” are sometimes held to be groupings that divide reality “at
its joints” – naturally, as it were.
Intuitively,
the idea is to draw a distinction between divisions that are somehow
fundamental – such as, paradigmatically, the atomic
differences between gold and lead or, perhaps, the constellation of
genetic differences between Homo sapiens and Australopithecus
afarensis – and divisions that
are somehow secondary – such, as differences between Indo-European
peoples are Afro-Asiatic peoples. The former would be candidates for
the title natural kinds.
On
this sort of a view, the Christian could maintain that the property
being a Christian (as
opposed to being a non-Christian)
is more like the property of being a speaker of an
Indo-European language (instead
of being a speaker of something else)
than it is like the property of being a specimen of the
genus Homo and the
species sapiens (instead of
belonging to some other genus and species). I take it that this is
entirely plausible.
The
point, here, is twofold. Number one, your original bird analogy is
faulty. You have two options. On the one hand, you could correct the
analogy. I myself suggested a correction. The problem for you is that
the corrected analogy seems better suited to make a point
diametrically opposed to the one that you wish to make. To put it
differently, the corrected bird analogy seems to suggest that actions
are inessential qualities and do not determine the essence of a
thing. Hence, one might think that the bird analogy provides no
support for the idea that Christians are “defined” by their
actions.
On
the other hand, you could abandon or replace the analogy. In this
case, I have suggested one possible Christian reply in advance. It
isn't at all clear that the membership (or “kind-ship”)
conditions for (potential) natural kinds like “bird” will be
relevantly similar to the conditions for non-natural sortals like
“Christian.” You owe us an argument or a new analogy – or both.
Later,
you assert: >>...being a Christian is like being pregnant -
either you are, or you are not<<
On
the face of it, the property of being pregnant
seems perhaps to be a bit more promising for you than being
a bird. For instance, being
pregnant isn't likely to be
mistaken for a natural kind – as though, amongst the furniture of
reality, one encounters the elements, the electrons, and the
pregnant. And it is agreed that the property of being
pregnant is metaphysical – it
obtains whether or not the female is aware of it – a point
reinforced by those unlikely cases that crop up from time to time in
the press where a woman who gives birth is alleged to have been
surprised by the event.
Your
case, however, has to have more to it than facts of physiology –
however undeniable they may be. Your burden, after all, is to show
that being Christian
is a property that is instantiated in virtue of a set of
obedience-oriented behavioral proclivities. This you have not argued
for in the least. You merely lay it down as a beginning principle. I
will have more to say about this stipulative habit of yours in PART
THREE.
Presently,
let me merely say that Christians of both Catholic and Protestant
persuasions may happily accede to the point of the pregnancy analogy.
Consider first Catholics. Catholics, we may say – too roughly for
most serious purposes, but adequate for the time being – endorse a
sort of view where being Christian
is something of a synonym for being a member of the
(Visible) Church. To the
Catholic, this membership is as definite – metaphysically speaking
– as is being pregnant.
Hence, the Catholic could agree that “being a Christian is like
being pregnant – either you are, or you are not” and yet deny that
this has anything whatever to do with “every tenet” of the Bible.
And you have said not a word against this alternative account.
As
for the Protestant, some indeed seem to cash out the property of
being a Christian in a
more epistemology-heavy way. To the Protestant – again, very
roughly – Christians are also called “believers” who have
membership (in virtue of their belief) in an invisible church, whose
roster is known only to God. To say, though, that the conception is
epistemology-heavy is not to say that it has no metaphysical
“anchor.” After all, to the Protestant, a true believer will have
a very definite belief in her mind. So, the Protestant could simply
say, “Right. 'Being a Christian *is* like being pregnant - either
you are, or you are not'” and yet still not agree that this amounts
to something that involves “every tenet”, etc., etc. For the
Protestant can simply say that whether the proper belief is found in
a person's mind is itself, metaphysically, a matter-of-fact. And as
far as I can see, nothing that you have said so far casts any doubt
on this.
Finally,
you raise the specter of “Constitutionality.” It isn't clear
whether there is any point of analogy. One reason to think this is
that it seems that the “Constitution” analogy redirects focus –
again, unceremoniously – away from the individual (singularly); and
not simply to the to the Church (collectively), but to the laws of
the Church. You don't explain this redirection, or even admit to it.
But it is plausibly there. After all, consider that individuals in a
nation – that is, citizens of a country – are not themselves said to be
“unconstitutional” or “constitutional.” (People don't seem to be the sorts of things that can be "unconstitutional," but people do seem to be the sorts of things that can be Christian. So, probably, the properties - un/Constitutional and un/Christian – are relevantly dissimilar.) Even the government
itself – contrary to your idiosyncratic usage – is not usually
the bearer of these properties. Rather, it is the government's
proposed laws
(in the case of the legislature) or enforcement
tactics (in the case
of the executive) or decisions
(in the case of the judiciary) that bear these properties. Why the
shift? You don't say. Hence, it isn't clear to me that there is any
obvious lesson to draw from musings about the Constitution. [For
another set of concerns, see END NOTE # 5]
But
in the interest of charity, here is what seems to me to be your
argument.
1.
If the Bible is the "constitution of Christianity," then a
person must obey every tenet of it in order to count as "Christian."
2.
The Bible is the "constitution of Christianity."
Therefore,
3.
A person must obey every tenet of it in order to count as
"Christian."
The
argument, as I have represented it, is formally valid. To put it
slightly differently, if the premises are true, then the conclusion
is true.
However,
I think that the argument is unsound.
The
most obvious place of attack is premise 2. Why think that "the
Bible is the 'constitution of Christianity'"?
You
have given very little by way of support of this premise, opining
only that it seems to you that the Bible:
"...establishes
and defines the tenets, requirements and the very existence of
Christianity".
I
have commented elsewhere that the notion that the Bible *establishes*
"the very existence of Christianity" is simply a confusion
of epistemic and metaphysical concerns. The Bible - specifically, the
New Testament - may well be a "window" to the establishment
of Christianity, that is, one of the means by which we have come to
know about it. But the Bible (presumably, the New Testament is in
focus) did not "establish" Christianity. Some of the
creedal formulations quoted by Saint Paul (e.g., in I Corinthians
15), as early as they are, still date from several years after the
crucifixion (say, ca. AD 35) and, as such, would post-date the
nascent Christian movement. The earliest epistles (e.g., I & II
Thessalonians and Galatians) probably date from between AD 45 - 50.
By this time, the early Christians were already meeting regularly in
one another's houses and, in fact, many were still attending
synagogue services. The point is, the Christian movement was in full
swing by the time the New Testament was fully set forth. But if
Christianity preceded the New Testament, then the New Testament
didn't “establish” Christianity. (QED)
Catholics
in particular have absolutely no reason to accept your assertions,
here. In the Catholic view, "Sacred Tradition" is a broad
category that ranges over the Apostles' oral teachings, stemming from
their lived experience with Jesus. To be sure, Catholics understand
Holy Scripture to be an important and very special subset of this
overall Sacred Tradition. However, for Catholics, Holy Scripture does
not exhaust Sacred Tradition. Therefore, while it may be that some of
the "tenets" and "requirements" of Christian
"faith and practice" are set forth in the Scripture
(Bible), there is no reason - antecedently - to suppose that this is
exhaustive.
However,
this sketch of a postive (Catholic-leaning) argument against premise
2 assumes a burden that need not be assumed. Again, you need to
defend your premise if you wish for it to be accepted. You produce no
quotations, citations, or even allusions to any Bible passages. You
simply and baldly assert that the Bible is the "Constitution"
of Christianity.
The
Protestant, therefore (and the Catholic as well), can simply deny
your premise with as much speed as you initially asserted it.
There are enough differences between the Bible and the Constitution
to make any sustained comparison highly suspect. [See, again, END
NOTE # 5]
In
any case, we needn't tarry on this discussion of premise 2. For in
addition to denying premise 1, the Christian can - and in my opinion
should - deny premise 1.
Actually,
to be a bit more cautious, Premise 1 is ambiguous. To put it a
different way, Premise 1 has more than one possible meaning. Let me
show what two of these are.
Call
the first disambiguation the "Electronic Counting Machine"
premise:
1*.
If the Bible is the "constitution of Christianity," then a
person must robotically obey every single tenet, of every single era
of "heilsgeschichte," in order to count as "Christian."
Call
the second disambiguation the "Hand Counted" premise:
1**.
If the Bible is the "constitution of Christianity," then a
person must obey every tenet of it that is presently in force, in
order to count as "Christian."
Both
Protestants and Catholics can point out, for example, that certain
passages in the New Testament plausibly abrogate various portions of
the Old Testament (see, e.g., Jeremiah 31:31-34; Matthew 9:17 // Mark
2:22; Hebrews Ch. 8, esp. vv. 7 & 13). In Protestant circles
alone there are no fewer than five distinct conceptions of the
relationship between testaments. [END NOTE # 6] But your facile
treatment gives unfamiliar readers the impression that the matters
are obvious. This is either naïve of you or misleading - or both.
Contrary to your dismissive rhetoric, fastidious interpretation (that
is, a sound and sober hermeneutic) is of the utmost importance. [See
PART THREE, Subsection C]
In
any case, the verdict should be this: Christians should deny premise
1*, but could - and I think ought to - accept premise 1** (well, that is, accept the consequent clause; the antecedent remains "iffy" - at best).
Subsection
B: Simplifications regarding the provision of an adequate account of
liberty.
Firstly,
your apparent suggested definition of “liberty” is both highly
contentious and arguably substandard.
You
wrote: >>...as a Christian you are NOT at liberty at all...You
cannot do as you please...<<
From
the above excerpt it would appear as though you are suggesting that
“liberty” be defined as being able to do as one pleases.
I
note three things. Number one, you have not argued that this
definition of “liberty” is superior to other contenders. Indeed,
you have evinced no awareness that there are
other contenders. You have merely laid it down that “liberty,” in
the relevant sense, is being able to do as one pleases.
Clearly,
we could mean this. But, number two, the notion is far too
loose. I doubt that many people, if pressed, would accept this
unqualified form. For example, suppose it would “please” me to
able to jump from my roof and fly away. On your definition, then, I
am arguably “...NOT at liberty at all [since I] cannot do as I
please.” This is absurd, however. If this be (< - subjunctive)
the definition, then “liberty” is an empty term and no one is at
liberty.
This
unhappy conclusion is, in any case, an unnecessary one as well. For,
number three, there are numerous other candidate definitions. Your
neglect of these alternatives not only generates absurd results (as
above), it also does an injustice to the topic since you explicitly
give readers the impression that Christians are simply helpless in
the face of your criticism. In fact, this impression is defective.
Amongst
the alternative candidate definitions, perhaps the option that is
most obviously compatible with Christianity would be to construe
“liberty” as the ability to choose the Good.
One
might think that this definition is trivial, but this would be a
mistake. Calvinists, for one thing, famously (or infamously,
depending on one's point of view) deny that humans ARE at liberty
without God's saving grace. To a Calvinist, recall, human beings are
born into a condition termed total depravity. On this account,
people are, therefore, unable to choose the Good unless and
until God acts first on their wills (by way of bestowing “irresistible
grace”) and enables them to choose the Good.
In
any case, the point is that “liberty” as the ability to choose
the Good is neither trivial nor obvious. More importantly, such a
definition resolves your dilemma. Being “BOUND to the laws and will
of God” simply entails that one is obliged to choose the Good.
Since, on this account, having “liberty” means being able to
choose the Good, there is no difficulty in the conjunction of being
“bound” to God and having liberty. Nowhere have you foreclosed on
this possibility.
A
related, and to my mind no less viable, option is a definition of
“liberty” very close to what you yourself offered – importantly
qualified and augmented. For example, “liberty” could be
construed as being able to act according to one's desires (within
natural limits). Of course, now the Christian need only add that
one's desires be conformed to the Good.
To
show how this resolves the difficulty that you pose, consider
the case of a person who actually desires the Good. A person
who desires the Good can, in your turn of phrase, be “BOUND to the
laws and will of God” without any sacrifice of liberty since, ex
hypothesi, God “binds” the person to do what they would want
to do anyway. Again, nothing that you have so far written precludes
this option.
Subsection
C: Simplifications regarding the function of, and need for,
interpretation.
You
wrote: >>Most [Christians?] do not [understand Christian
doctrine and live by it]. These are the people that must "interpret"
the Bible to mean what they want it to mean, or to adhere to the
lives they live, rather than fully understanding the Bible and living
by it - which would require a very comprehensive change in the way
they live. ...Either you want to live by every tenet of the Bible and
nothing more, or you do not. You do not "interpret" the
tenets of the faith to fit your desired lifestyle. You desire the
lifestyle that comes with those tenets.<<
Here
it is important to get clear on terminology. In my lexicon, and in
the area of literary studies, “interpret” simply means (something
like) extract meaning out of (a text). So, if my sister sends
me a card, then I will read the card and try to understand what she
has written. I will try to extract her intended meaning out of the
words that she used. Or, in short, I will interpret her card.
In
this sense, we interpret constantly. We interpret newspaper articles,
road signs, text messages, and so on. It is difficult, therefore
(impractical, if not naturally impossible), to put aside the issue of
interpretation (in this broad sense). In the matter at hand, I have
to interpret your post and you have to interpret the replies that are
posted.
Of
course, in general, this sort of interpretation is nearly automatic.
We seldom reflect on the process at all (still less frequently do we
catalog the procedures) – unless, that is, something goes wrong.
Hurt feelings may be our first sign that something has been
misinterpreted.
To
be sure, people may have psychological peculiarities that impede
mutual understanding, and we each no doubt sometimes express
ourselves in idiosyncratic ways. By and large, though, interpretation of one
another's communications is pretty straightforward – in the sense
of being an “everyday,” run-of-the-mill procedure.
There
is an academic discipline called “hermenenutics," understood
in the sense of some bundle of methods for interpreting texts. This
discipline addresses itself to interpretive efforts that are not
everyday events.
This
is nothing about which to be alarmed. Hermeneutics is an important
component of literature studies of all sorts. To give just a taste
of this, intuitively, poetry and prose will be reviewed differently.
So hermeneutics will set forth procedures for interpreting texts
according to genre.
Since
the Bible can be analyzed as literature, one can study biblical
hermeneutics as well. The reason that one needs,
self-consciously, to have a method for interpreting the Bible, but
one can usually interpret one's birthday cards and newspaper articles
without a conscious method, is (roughly) that the authors of the
Bible did not share our “context” (broadly speaking). The
biblical authors lived in quite different cultures, at quite
different times, surrounded by quite different geographies. And,
indeed, they spoke and wrote in quite different languages (from us
and, sometimes, from each other). Extracting the intended meaning
from texts produced in such different circumstances requires greater
care, and a more deliberate approach.
However,
you seem to use the word “interpret” quite differently. From your
pen, “interpret” seems to carry the sense often conveyed in
ordinary speech by locutions such as “explain away” or, perhaps,
“re-interpret.” To try to be more precise, “explain
away” seems to come down to (something like) all of the following:
to extract the genuine meaning out of something, judge the meaning
too sensitive, and try to obscure, “cover up,” or otherwise
modify the meaning or the text itself in order to make the meaning
more palatable.
To
be sure, it is doubtless true that people may obscure,
“cover up,” or otherwise modify particular meanings (or even
various texts themselves) in order to make particular meanings (or
texts) more palatable. However, this additional exercise of
concealment is not part of “interpretation-simpliciter.”
So
we have two ways to go, terminologically speaking.
Number
one, we could follow the usual terminology. If we follow the usual
terminology, then “interpret” will mean interpret-simpliciter,
that is, simply to extract meaning from a text.
We can then call the additional acts of “cover-up” and
“explaining away” something like concealment.
On
this way of speaking, when confronted with a text (for example, some
passage of the Bible), the first
step will be to read and interpret the text (which is sometimes no easy task). Once the genuine meaning
has been extracted, that is, once the text has been properly
interpreted, a reader then has a choice. And here, at least when
dealing with some sort of didactic passage, the choice is indeed as
you have put it. On the one hand, a person can look at the genuine
interpretation and choose to conform his or her life to it, or a
person could decline to so conform. This declination could take four
forms (at least – the following terms are simply my suggestions):
-
Simple rejection,
where the reader, while acknowledging the true interpretation and not
seeking to modify it, just flatly refuses to conform to it;
-
Concealment (what you
seem most concerned about), where the reader willfully and purposely
distorts the acknowledged true interpretation for one reason or
other;
-
Agnostic suspension,
where the reader professes, whether in good faith or not, to be
unsure of the genuine interpretation and therefore unable to
understand what conformity would involve; and
-
Indifference, where
the reader simply professes not to care one way or the other either
what the text means, or what conformity would involve.
The
key point is that, on my schema (which is standard in
grammatical-historical hermeneutics), “interpretation” and
“concealment” are distinct actions and should not be confused or
conflated. The former is simply a name for the process of extracting
the genuine meaning from a text (as well as a name for the genuine
meaning so extracted), whereas the latter is a name for an act of
willful defacement of the genuine interpretation.
Number
two, we could follow your terminology. If we follow your terminology,
then “(re-)interpret” itself will mean “explain away.” To
translate: “(Re-)interpret” in your lexicon is “concealment”
in mine. This difference appears to be verbal only and poses no
problem PROVIDED THAT we carefully track whose lexicon we are
following. But if we do follow you, we will find it useful to coin a
term to refer to the initial act of extracting meaning from texts.
At
this point, you might object that no term other than “read” is
necessary. I think, however, that this is simply mistaken. Here are a
few reasons and examples that may us help to see this.
First,
if “reading” and “extracting genuine meaning” were identical
actions, then it should be practically impossible to read a text
without automatically extracting the correct meaning from it.
However, this leaves no room for honest mistakes. If reading a text
always elicited in the reader an apprehension of the genuine meaning,
then any instance of “misinterpretation” would have to be the
product of nefarious intent. This seems extreme, uncharitable, and
simply wrongheaded. Despite the fact that intentional distortion of
meanings surely does occur, still it seems obvious that there are
innumerable instances of honest misunderstandings, to say nothing of
misunderstandings that are neither honest nor dishonest (e.g., those
due to laziness, negligence, or sheer stupidity).
Second,
If both “reading” and “extracting genuine meaning” designate
the same action, then there should be no texts that can be read
without being understood. However, this seems more obviously false
than did the notion that all “misinterpretations” are
dishonorable.
For
one thing, we are sometimes able to read passages that, if we are
honest, we would say we had difficulty understanding. Consider these
lines from Lewis Carroll's poem, Jabberwocky.
“`Twas brillig, and the slithy toves | Did gyre and gimble in the
wabe.” Perhaps intuitions differ, but my impulse is to say that
while I can read the lines, I am hard pressed to make sense of them.
One
might object that the trouble with Carroll's poem is that he employs
neologisms that, were they familiar to the reader, would not impede
meaning-extraction. I should resist this response, but if one is
impressed by it, then consider a further illustration, which employs
no neologisms: “For purposes of paragraph (3), an organization
described in paragraph (2) shall be deemed to include an organization
described in section 501(c)(4), (5), or (6) which would be described
in paragraph (2) if it were an organization described in section
501(c)(3).” The Economist
article titled “The hardest sentence in the tax code” notes that
this “sentence is so infamous [that] Ronald Reagan cited it in his
drive to pass the simplifying tax reform of 1986” (humorously, the
offending sentence remained even after the supposed Reaganite
“simplification”). This sentence contains only “regular”
words of Standard American English. Yet, I should say that even
availing oneself of the full text of the embedded references does
little to make this sentence more comprehensible on its own.
Just
for good measure, let me take one more stab at illustrating. Consider
the statement, “John does not think that we should stop investing
in companies that are not against gun control.” Assuming that
“reading” and “meaning extraction” are the same event, one
should not have to do anything more than read sentences like this in
order to understand them. However, if you are like me in this, I find
myself having to stop and analyze the sentence into components to be
sure that I have understood it correctly. Reading the words appears
to be one thing. I have no difficulty with any of the words,
individually. Moreover, I can read the sequence of words without
trouble. But when it comes to the question of what the sentence
means, I find myself having to stop and do much more mental work than
simply articulating words. [END NOTE # 7]
If
all of this is correct – or even close to correct – then we need
some way to mark off the task of extracting meaning from a text and
distinguish it from the bare act of reading. If you wish to use the
word “interpret” for what I have called “concealment,” then
you need an alternative word to mark off what I have called
“interpretation-simpliciter.” Suppose, just for the present, we
select the word “elucidate.” Then, following you, step one would
be to read and elucidate a particular text.
Once
the genuine meaning of a text has been extracted, that is, once the
text has been properly elucidated, a reader then has the same choice
that I outlined, above. On the one hand, a person can look at the
elucidation and choose to conform his or her life to it, or a person
could decline to conform. And this takes the form of the same
fourfold declination that I previously sketched, with one change. In
place of the term “concealment” (which was my term), we use
“(re-)interpret” (which was your term). So one could:
-
Simply reject the elucidation,
where the reader, while acknowledging the true elucidation and not
seeking to modify it, just flatly refuses to conform to it;
-
(Re-)Interpret the elucidation,
where the reader willfully and purposely distorts the acknowledged
true elucidation for one reason or other;
-
Agnostically suspend action,
where the reader professes, whether in good faith or not, to be
unsure of the genuine elucidation and therefore unable to understand
what conformity would involve; or
-
Remain indifferent,
where the reader simply professes not to care one way or the other
either what the text means, or what conformity would involve.
The
key point is that, seemingly even on your schema (which is
idiosyncratic and, I think, not preferable, but still manageable),
“elucidation” and “(re-)interpretation” should be understood to be
distinct actions and should not be confused or conflated. The former
is simply the name for the process of extracting the genuine meaning
from a text (as well as a name for the genuine meaning so extracted),
whereas the latter is a name for an act of willful defacement of the
genuine elucidation.
However,
once we have untangled the terminology, it should be clear that
before one jumps into accusations of textual maleficence (whether
understood to be “concealment” in my sense, or
“(re-)interpretation” in yours), one needs to establish, by
argument and exegesis, the genuine meaning of the text in question
(the “interpretation” in my sense, or the “elucidation” in
yours). [See END NOTE # 8]
This
is not trivial. The Bible is often a very difficult – if profound –
collection of documents. I should not think it even remotely
plausible to hold that the genuine interpretations-elucidations are
in any sense usually “transparent.” Even Protestants who hold to
the “Perspicuity of Scripture,” generally hold that it is the
guiding light of the Holy Spirit which renders the text clear –
not, in the first place, the transparency of the text itself or, in
the second place, the acumen of the reader. (It should be noted that
the “Perspicuity of Scripture” is not a Catholic conception.)
[END NOTE # 9]
Therefore,
the point is that, as things stand there seem to be two possibilities. You might have a woefully naïve
and inadequate view of hermeneutics – that is, if you really hold that the
meaning of Bible passages is, on the whole or even on “average,”
transparent or obvious. If this is the case, you need to do far more
than simply assert that the meanings are obvious! You need to do some
heavy lifting in order to actually evidence this opinion. One place
to start would be to actually begin reproducing Scripture quotations,
providing us with your proposed analyses of them.
Alternatively,
you might have a view that, if you take on board my addition of the
category of “elucidation,” comes down, in the end, to the same
thing as “my” schema. In this case, elucidation precedes the
choice of whether to conform to or conceal the true meaning of the text.
We might then agree, procedurally at least. The project would
then be one of trying to actually extract the correct meaning from a
given passage. And, again, the obvious starting point would be to
reproduce a Scripture passage and begin to analyze it. [See END NOTE
# 8]
PART
THREE – STRAW MEN
Recall
that “[t]he 'straw man' fallacy is committed when an arguer
distorts an opponent's argument for the purpose of more easily
attacking it...[T]he kind of distortion...is often an attempt to
exaggerate...”. [END NOTE # 10]
One
difficulty that pervades your text is that you repeatedly stipulate
various “definitions” or “requirements” for being a
Christian, but it is not at all clear why any Christian should accept
them. [END NOTE # 11]
For
example, your wrote: >>So, if you do not live by
every tenet of the Bible, you are not a Christian.<<
Now,
I acknowledge that you have given at least one argument. Above, I
responded to my (I hope charitable and accurate) formalization of
that argument by denying both of its premises. I do not want to
needlessly lengthen this reply by repeating myself. What I wish to
emphasize here is that your text reads like so much armchair
speculation. This sort of exercise can be productive and, believe you
me, my own chair is well-worn. But in matters such as historical
controversies (in which, presently, we're up past our ears),
speculation can only replace investigation at the expense of grave
disservice to the topic.
You
simply assert that the true criterion for being Christian is
such-and-so. You provide no quotation from any of Christianity's
historic creeds to buttress your claim, despite the fact that there
is no shortage of creedal material. The eminent nineteenth century
church historian Philip Schaff penned a three volume set titled The
Creeds of Christendom (1884),
running well over 2,000 pages, on just this very subject.
Additionally,
you quote no Christain theologians and, indeed, show no awareness of
Christianity's rich theological history. My shelves contain no fewer
than 76 volumes solely from Church Fathers writing around the Council of
Nicea. The collection of works in theology has only been expanded
since that time with important contributions by such notables as
Martin Luther and John Calvin, and, since even those luminaries, by
innumerable lesser lights. And yet, you reproduce not a line of any
of this text. You provide nothing by way of evidence that your
proposed criterion has ever been seriously advanced by any serious
Christian theologian – at any time – during the entire history of
the Church.
Moreover,
you do not even quote from the Bible, despite making the centerpiece
of your proposal various claims about what, according to you, the
Bible says or implies and what bad news this spells for Christians.
Then, as a flourish, you assert that all of this is very transparent
and easily discovered.
Furthermore,
you seem to be unaware that there are massive debates over the very
issues that you discuss – namely, in what does Christianity
consist? This involves other issues in the vicinity such as what
constitutes “salvation”? What is the relationship between the
Testaments? What is the relationship between “Israel” and the
Church? What are the natures of God's various covenants with men? And
much else besides.
Insofar
as you want or expect to be taken seriously, this unintentional
ignorance or willful neglect of the vast ocean of Christian output
concerning the topic about which you proclaim yourself occupied is
nothing short of hubris. If, indeed, you are merely just tossing
thoughts about willy nilly – perhaps not aiming to produce an
argument based upon sound evidence (and succeeding), perhaps typing a
“manifesto” of some sort – then, maybe, your ignorance or
neglect are excusable. But in this case, it should be absolutely
clear that neither Christians nor anyone else has even the slightest
reason (evidentially speaking) to take you seriously.
Perhaps
most outrageously, you seem indifferent to the fact that your entire
presentation aims to speak for, and define, “Christianity” on a
monumental scale and yet, you casually (and probably unconsciously)
take sides in debates that have raged for hundreds of years
(conservatively counted) without even so much as one scintilla of the
evidence that one would expect of such serious judgments.
For
example, you abruptly remark: >>...if it is not found in the
Bible, it is not a command of God.<<
Amazingly,
with a single statement you manage both to smuggle in unannounced the
Protestant “formal principle” sola scriptura (over which Christianity split during the Reformation), as well as
virtually take sides in an important point of contention between
Lutherans and Calvinists – with Lutherans historically holding, as
a so-called “Regulative Principle,” that “Whatever is not
forbidden in Scripture is permissible” and Calvinists maintaining
(perhaps closer to you) that “Whatever is not commanded in
Scripture is forbidden.” [END NOTE # 12]
What
arguments do you advance for your semi-Calvinistic conclusions? What
rebuttals do you provide for Lutherans? Do you have a revised Ordo
Salutis for theologians to inspect? For these debates are
situated in broader contexts.
One
such contextual element is the host of Catholic-Protestant issues
that you leave untouched. Your statement, both previously quoted and
discussed, that: >>The Bible...establishes and defines the
tenets, requirements and the very existence of Christianity...<<
reads to me like a blunt endorsement of Sola Scriptura – the
“...Reformation principle that Scripture – not Scripture plus
church tradition – is the [sole] source of Christian revelation.”
[END NOTE # 13]
I
personally spent over two years – suspended between Catholicism and
Protestantism – thinking about this one issue (before “reverting”
back to Catholicism from Evangelicalism). I have more than 30 books,
and countless articles, on the topic. In fact, if I continue on to do
PhD work this is one possible topic that I would consider to be
developable into a fruitful dissertation. And yet you ally yourself with the "Protestant side" almost as lightly and self-assuredly as if you were announcing that "grass is green."
The
point – if I have not already belabored it – is that the
questions that you are touching on are complex, subtle, deeply rooted
in history, and not easily resolved.
CONCLUDING REMARKS
As
I said in my introduction, I am thrilled by your interest and I
applaud your enthusiasm. But it would be a huge understatement to say
that the sort of work which could make a contribution towards
clarifying or tracing out – let alone untangling – even the
thinnest thread in this dense tapestry would, minimally, be a
meticulously constructed piece whose every phrase was carefully
measured (probably measured twice). As much as I admire your energy
and appreciate your indefatigable efforts to expose the dark goings
on of crypto-politics, with all due respect, your (a)theological
musings, while perhaps “Like-able" by some in a shallow, Facebook-ian sense, have nothing like the evidentiary
depth of some of your political e-pamphleteering (which I have found
edifying).
In
six paragraphs, bereft of even the fainest hint of a citation, a
conscientious reader may detect one logical contradiction, two
category confusions/conflations, multiple oversimplifications, and
contentious (at best) and spurious (at worst) attributions verging on
the erection of a classic straw man.
The
relevant themes are immense in their breadth. One either needs to
immerse oneself in the relevant literature (much as you have begun to
do with the Founders) or, frankly, leave the topic alone.
~ Matthew J. Bell, 23 February 2013
~FINIS~
***
END NOTES ***
END
NOTE #1 – “A logical contradiction is the conjunction of a
statement [S] and it's denial [not-S]. … [For example,] I love you
and I don't love you.” (Source: G. Randolph Mayes, "Logical
Consistency and Contradiction," Sacramento State U,
<http://www.csus.edu/indiv/m/mayesgr/phl4/Handouts/phl4contradiction.htm>.)
END
NOTE # 2 – Here I am having a few difficulties with the phrase
“comprehensively familiar with every word”. Firstly, there seem
to be two possible meanings for the word “familiar” and I am
unsure which (if either) you had in mind. Breaking out my trusty
dictionary, on the one hand I read that “familiar” can mean
"commonly or generally known or seen". So for example,
being a native St. Louisan, I have often driven on Highway 70. One
could fairly say that, to me, Highway 70 is "commonly or
generally known or seen". For all of my “common and general”
familiarity with Highway 70, I should not pretend to be aware of
“every” nook and cranny – or even of the “details” of all
of it's main entrances and exits. Despite this, I think that I still
count as being “familiar” with Highway 70. I would be hard
pressed to accurately present a reasonably detailed map of even a
small portion of the Highway. So, in a similar way, in “common and
general” sense, I simply fail to see how “familiarity” with the
Bible needs to consist of awareness of “every word.” This is to
say that you might be confusing “familiarity” with (something
like) exhaustive awareness. If so, it is not at all clear why
a person has to have “exhaustive knowledge” of the Bible before
that person could count as a Christian.
Maybe
this is too quick, however. For there is another definition of the
word “familiar.” Perhaps you intended this other definition. On
the other hand, then, “familiar” can mean “Well known from long
or close association". In this case, the idea of something's
being “well known” is baked into the relevant definition. Thus,
it seems that this second definition does conjoin “familiarity”
with (at least something close to) “exhaustive awareness.”
(Strictly, it seems very likely to me that “exhaustive awareness”
is probably practically impossible to attain. But, one could think of
something like very roughly like being “really aware” if not
literally “exhaustively aware.”) Indeed, you don't just use the
word “familiar” by itself. Instead, you coin the phrase
“comprehensively familiar.” So it seems that I am now on the
right track.
Two
things should be said, however. Number one, if by “comprehensively
familiar” you literally meant “exhaustive familiarity,” then
your additional phrase “every word” is simply superfluous. For,
it seems reasonably to think that one cannot be “comprehensively
familiar” with a text, in the sense of being “exhaustively
familiar” with it, unless one is “familiar” with “every
word.” Hence, “every word” is built in to “comprehensive
familiarity.” But maybe you were just being emphatic.
The
far more serious difficulty with the conception of “comprehensive
familiarity” is that you have given us to reason to accept this as
a requirement for being a “true Christian.” Catholics (as well as
Protestants who do not endorse the idea of a “gathered church”)
would seemingly all hold that some children (e.g., those who have been Baptized)
could be rightly be termed “Christians.” Clearly, very young
children (e.g., infants) will have no familiarity with the Bible –
let alone “comprehensive familiarity.”
Now
some might say, “Well, yeah, exactly...but that's why children
can't be 'Christians.'” However, my point is that you have given
me, as a Catholic Christian, absolutely no reason to take your
“requirement” seriously. You just assert that a Christian “must”
be “comprehensively familiar” with the Bible. I await your
defense of this “requirement.”
As
it stands, I think that “comprehensive familiarity” is
practically impossible for most people (with a document as large as
the Bible). Furthermore, since I think that infants can be
Christians (although, clearly not "advanced" or well-catechized ["discipled"] Christians), no sort of Bible “familiarity” is required at all for
being a Christian. But then, if no familiarity is required for being
a Christian, then (a fortiori) certainly “comprehensive
familiarity” is not required.
You
have seemingly confused being a Christian with being a
Bible scholar.
END
NOTE # 3 – James Van Cleve, “Essence/Accident,” Jaegwon Kim &
Ernest Sosa, Eds., A Companion to Metaphysics (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1995), p. 136.
END
NOTE # 4 – More more examples, see the Wikipedia article:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Flightless_bird.
END
NOTE # 5 – I have a few reservations about comparing the Bible to
the U.S. Constitution.
For
one thing, the U.S. Constitution is – very plausibly – a single,
continuous document comprised of a single genre, namely, it is a work
of positive law. (I still say “very plausibly” instead of
“definitely” because, traditionally, the Preamble is not treated
as positive law, but merely as introductory.) The Bible, on the other
hand, is a collection of discreet books (66 in the Protestant canon)
containing numerous, distinctive genres (e.g., historical narratives,
didactic passages, positive law, poetry, proverbs, apocalyptic
writing, etc.).
Moreover,
the U.S. Constitution was drafted and ratified over an approximately
two year period (from 1787-1789) by 55 delegates (in attendance),
which delegates shared much by way of common socio-cultural
background, from 12 states (Rhode Island did not send delegates). By
contrast (and bracketing issues relating to divine inspiration), the
Bible had roughly 40 different human authors, who wrote over a period
of at least 1,500 years, in various locations around the ancient
near-eastern world, in 3 different languages (chiefly Hebrew and
Greek but also, in portions, Aramaic).
Last,
but certainly not least, we should hastily add that the U.S.
Constitution was both drafted and consciously adopted to function as
the legal framework for a new nation, whereas the Bible, although
containing legal passages in parts (e.g., Deuteronomy), nevertheless
neither was drafted to be (in toto) a legal document, nor was
“adopted” (or in any clear way “ratified”) to serve as
anything other than a guide to religious faith and practice.
Now
these differences – to put it mildly – seem significant enough to
justify suspicions about drawing tidy parallels between the U.S.
Constitution and the Bible. Both are complex documents. But it is
doubtful that this complexity is a broad enough base with which to
connect them, or that they can be fairly or usefully considered to
serve anything like “the same purposes.”
END
NOTE # 6 – See, e.g., Greg L. Bahnsen, et. al., Five
Views on Law and Gospel (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1996).
END
NOTE # 7 – Another consideration in favor of the notion that simple
“reading” and more complex “meaning-extraction” are distinct,
is the observation that readers need training in skills such as
“identifying main ideas” and so on – training that goes beyond
bare literacy. This does not apply only to young readers. Mortimer J.
Adler's classic work, How to Read a Book (NY: Simon &
Schuster, 1940/1972), was written for general, adult audiences. It
seems highly dubious that a work would achieve “classic” status
(or anything remotely like it) if it's premise was entirely
superfluous. Adler's premise, of course, is that correctly extracting
meaning from a text involves more than merely correctly saying (out
loud or to oneself) the words on the page.
END
NOTE # 8 – One assumption that we both seem to share is that there
IS a definite meaning to texts like (at least some) Bible passages
and (at least some) lines of the U.S. Constitution. This is not an
assumption shared by everyone. Some people believe that audiences can
“create” meaning. In jargon, this is sometimes called “eisegesis”
(reading meaningINTO a text), to distinguish it from “exegesis”
(extracting meaning OUT OF a text).
END
NOTE # 9 – “The clarity [perspicuity] of Scripture means that the
Bible is written in such a way that its teachings are able to be
understood by all who will read it seeking God's help and being
willing to follow it.” Source: Wayne Grudem, Systematic Theology
(Grand Rapids, MI: IVP, 1994), p. 108.
END
NOTE # 10 – Patrick J. Hurley, A Concise Introduction to Logic,
Sixth Ed. (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1997), p. 129.
END
NOTE # 11 – One way to construe your “thesis” is that you seem
to be suggesting that there can be no “bad Christians.” One
either is a Christian, or isn't. Okay. But why should Christians
accept this conception, as opposed to an alternative? In fact, I
think that no Christian should accept your suggested “requirement.”
There is a very clear reason for this, I think. It is one that is
well familiar to students of law. To be more exact, one does not
predicate a present determination of fact on a future, unfulfilled condition.
For
example, in Catholicism, there are several preconditions for a
“valid” Reconciliation (that is, the Sacrament during which a
penitent confesses his or her sins to a priest in order to receive
absolution). They are (roughly, as set forth by the Baltimore
Catechism): The penitent: should have thoroughly examined his or her
conscience; should be sincerely sorry for his or her sins; should be
firmly committed to not committing those sins again; should honestly
and completely confess his or her sins to the priest; and should be
*willing to perform* the penance that the priest gives. Now I do not
wish to complicate matters with irrelevant wrangling about Catholic
sacraments. What I wish to draw attention to is this: The final
condition for a valid Reconciliation is that the penitent be *willing
to perform* his or her penance, not that the performance of the penance be fait accompli.
This is not a license to fail to perform one's penance. Rather, it is
further evidence of the fact that it is bad form to predicate present
decisions of fact upon future unfulfilled conditions. Provided that
all of the (present tenses) conditions are fulfilled, when the priest
pronounces absolution, the penitent, is (present tense) absolved from
his or her sins. Should the penitent die en route from his or her
confession, before performing the penance, such does not invalidate
the sacrament.
Or
again, on the Catholic view, adultery does not invalidate marriage
vows. Very generally, a marriage in valid insofar as the man and
woman freely and sincerely, in sufficient knowledge, consent to be
married. Future acts of infidelity are not ipso
facto
invalidating because, from the standpoint of the Sacrament of
Matrimony, unless one party, during the wedding ceremony itself,
intended to commit future acts of adultery, such acts represent
nebulous future possibilities that cannot justifiably be included in the present tense evaluation (at the time of the Matrimony) as to whether or not a marital union has been created successfully.
So,
you ask...what in the hell does this have to do with anything?
Well,
consider our options. Think of a Boy Scout. There is the so-called “Scout
Law,” expressed memorably (albeit roughly) by Bugs Bunny: “A
Scout is Trustworthy, Loyal, Helpful, Friendly, Courteous, Kind,
Obedient, Cheerful, Thrifty, Brave, Clean and helps little old ladies
across the street without expectation of recompense either.”
So
here are two poles, on the one hand we could say that is a Scout is a
person who successfully does all of those things throughout the
entirety of his life. There are two problems, one metaphysical and one epistemic. In this case, it seems, we could only decide (epistemically)
whether a person was, truly, a Scout or not after they had died.
Before death the most one could say is, “Well, he seems to be a
Scout so far, but who knows what he might do tomorrow?” Additionally, on this
view, at best, a person could flip flop – perhaps daily – between
being (metaphysically) a Scout and not or, at worst, a person couldn't count as a
Scout at all until his entire life could be evaluated. Several
difficulties arise. Firstly, it isn't clear who then could ever be
counted as a Scout. Maybe some people are okay with such a result,
however – this epistemic vagueness. Secondly, there is no such
thing as a “bad scout” on this view. This seems to me quite
counter-intuitive.
On
the other hand, we might say that a Scout is a person who aims to do
all of those things, but who, in fact, might mess up once – or
repeatedly. Here, a person remains a Scout as long as he says that's
what he is, and there can be both “good Scouts” and “bad
Scouts.”
Christianity,
I think, provides a similar set of options. You have given no reason
to favor your conception. And the Christian has independent reasons
to suspect that you're wrong. From the Bible it seems that there will
be, so to speak, various degrees of reward in heaven and various
degrees of punishment in hell. Now one might explain degrees of
punishment by saying that not all ne'er do wells perform equally
badly. But why, on your view, should there be degrees of reward in
heaven? (E.g., Some will end up barely "...saved—even though only as one escaping through the flames" [1 Corinthians 3:15 NIV].)
END
NOTE # 12 – Robert C. Walton, Chronological and Background Charts
of Church History (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1986), Chart # 42.
END
NOTE # 13 – Stanley J. Grenz, David Guretzski, and Cherith Fee
Nordling, Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms (Downer's
Grove, IL: IVP, 1999), p. 108.
YoBit lets you to claim FREE COINS from over 100 unique crypto-currencies, you complete a captcha once and claim as much as coins you want from the available offers.
ReplyDeleteAfter you make about 20-30 claims, you complete the captcha and continue claiming.
You can click on claim as many times as 30 times per one captcha.
The coins will stored in your account, and you can exchange them to Bitcoins or any other currency you want.